Justin Thacker

Why I Dislike Effective Altruism

ea-og-image-1200x650Effective Altruism (EA), one of the latest movements in the aid efficacy debate, is in reality not much more than a 21stCentury version of 19thCentury utilitarianism. And while utilitarianism has some value as an ethical theory, it should not be used to dictate all ethical decisions. In the same way, EA has some value, but is not the metanarrative for aid efficacy that its advocates would like us to think.

The fundamental tenet of EA is that we should make decisions regarding our charitable giving based on the effectiveness of the charities we support. Such effectiveness is measured numerically by means of the outcomes achieved per dollar of support that is provided. EA is therefore a form of consequentialism and beneficial outcomes might include measures such as Quality Adjusted Life Years (QALYs). Health outcomes are not the only ones that EA advocates champion, but they are one of the most prevalent as they have a good pedigree in the medical literature. EA especially likes the use of randomised controlled trials in evaluating the outcomes of development interventions.

While this approach seems perfectly reasonable, it falls foul of precisely the same critiques that have been levelled at 19thCent utilitarianism, namely that humans are notoriously bad at predicting and assessing all the relevant outcomes of their activities so these are the reasons I reject EA.

  1. Not everything that is beneficial is measurable

There’s a classic story about a development project that was seeking to improve school enrolment. As part of this project, community leaders were paid in response to the proportion of children that attended school. The project was a phenomenal success with rates of school enrolment increasing to near 100%. EA would no doubt have championed this project as one worthy of support, except that eventually someone actually visited the project. What they found was ‘classes’ of 50 or 60 children with no teachers, no teaching, no resources, simply children sitting in empty classrooms with nothing else going on. These children were enrolled; they just weren’t doing any learning. In response, an EA advocate might recognise that school enrolment is not the relevant measure, but rather the number of teachers, or quantity of resources, but again that is not what really matters. What actually counts in education is learning gain, but that is actually far more difficult to measure and depends on a huge range of other factors including prior learning, valid and reliable tests, and an appropriate measure. In the UK, we have been trying to measure learning gain for the last 40 years and still haven’t quite found a solution let alone even attempt it at higher education. My point is that as soon as we choose one thing to measure then, unsurprisingly, the efforts of the providers go into improving that measure, and that measure alone. This problem is even more significant when we consider some contingencies that are highly relevant to development outcomes, but perhaps by definition unmeasurable. How for instance do you measure someone’s sense of dignity and self-worth, or community relations, or a sense of entrepreneurship or resilience? All of this matters for development, but according to EA, if we can’t measure it, we should discount it, and therein lies the problem.

  1. EA ignores the wider impacts of our activity

In his bookDoing Good Better, William Macaskill, one of the co-founders of EA spends much time encouraging an ‘Earning to Give’ approach to altruism. The basis of ‘Earning to Give’ is that for some of us we can do far more ‘good’ if we seek careers in which we earn as much as we can with a view to donating a good proportion of those lifetime earnings to effective charitable causes.

There are a number of concerns that I have with this model, but my primary one is that it ignores the ethical impact of many high earning jobs. One of the spin offs from EA, 80,000 hours, responds to this critique thus:

…many (but not all) financial traders make profits at the expense of other traders, so they’re moving money around, mostly from rich people to other rich people. Of course, there are some people who cause harm in these industries, but that’s true of any industry.

So the message seems to be – there’s only a small amount of harm in these high-earning jobs, and that is outweighed by all the charitable donations that these higher earners make. If that were true, there would be nothing to object to, but it is not. In my book, Global Poverty, I drew attention to the way in which the West is a net drain on African resources to the tune of $60 bn a year. We like to think that cumulatively the West donates to sub-Saharan Africa, but in reality we extract far more than we give. Such extraction takes the form of debt servicing, climate change adaptation and especially tax evasion.And the companies doing this are not small, local ones, but the large multinationals – the ones that provide the high-earning jobs. I once got engaged with a large communications companies in West Africa who were offering to sponsor our healthcare work in that part of the world. It all sounded very good until I realized that the very same company was engaged in a range of extractive industries that failed to pay appropriate taxes in the country where they worked. This company would have done far more good if they had stopped their philanthropic work and paid their taxes.

  1. EA does nothing to address the root causes of poverty

Give a man a fish and he’ll eat for a day, teach him to fish and he’ll eat for a lifetime. It’s a lovely aphorism, but in the current global economic system, the truth is that we need to stop polluting his fishing lake, stop extracting all the fish without paying for them and stop charging the man to borrow a fishing rod and fish in his own lake. The problem with EA is that its frame of reference is far too narrow. It rightly asks the question as to which charities are most effective but it fails to ask the question, why are those charities needed in the first place? As Martin Luther King reminded us:

On the one hand we are called to play the good Samaritan on life’s roadside; but that will be only an initial act. One day we must come to see that the whole Jericho road must be transformed so that men and women will not be constantly beaten and robbed as they make their journey on life’s highway. True compassion is more than flinging a coin to a beggar; it is not haphazard and superficial. It comes to see that an edifice which produces beggars needs restructuring.

Of course, the root causes of poverty are complex and certainly not easily solvable. They go back to our colonial history, our approach to fostering debt, our contributions to climate change and our current approach to international trade. But having recognized this, any response to poverty that is worthy of attention must in some sense seek to address these root causes. There is nothing in EA that makes any attempt to do this. Giving to causes that provide discrete services to the poor – however effective they are – will not provide a long term solution to poverty. Changing our current financial system, and terms of international trade might. I would therefore be a happy advocate of EA if its focus was on lobbying the national and international seats of power to provide a fairer system, but in its advocacy of ‘earning to give’, I fear it may be doing the precise opposite – propping up a system that keeps the poor poor while making all of us feel that little bit better about ourselves.

Advertisements

01/06/2018 Posted by | Uncategorized | , , , , | Comments Off on Why I Dislike Effective Altruism